This is a draft of a text I'm working on articulating a specifically Lutheran approach to religious liberty. I welcome comments and questions to refine and improve the essay.
--
On Religious Liberty
When developing a vocabulary of culture and
society, difficulties arise. It is the words themselves that often present
particular trouble. Conceptual words, what Raymond Williams calls keywords in his book of the same name,
are notoriously elusive. They have
specialized meanings in particular areas of study. Their usage is variable in
general discussions.
Williams wrote an entire book on keywords because
he found that with such words the problems of the meaning of the words are
"inextricably bound up with the problems it was being used to
discuss" (Introduction). In other words, the words themselves are elements
of the problem we are seeking to solve when we discuss that which the words are
intended to signify.
I have been given the task of writing an
essay on the understanding of religious liberty from a Lutheran perspective.
With "religious liberty," our troubles are twofold, for we have two
words tethered, both of them endlessly complicated. One of them made it (sort
of) into William's keyword lexicon, elucidated in neighboring entries on liberal and liberation in his lexicon.
If we take Williams as at least somewhat
authoritative, we learn that although liberty in general means freedom, the
more specific use of the term historically has been that of formal permission
or privilege. We "take" liberties. Other than this sense, liberty
also has the sense of rights granted under the auspices of some sovereign. Our
liberties are protected.
Williams offers another entry on liberation,
and notes that although historically liberation was understood as emancipation,
being set free from bondage, the more contemporary sense of liberation includes
a more active sense of winning self-determination. Our religious liberties are
ours; we own our own freedom.
I will circle back around to this term,
liberty, in a bit, offering a comparison to the word more appropriate to
Christian and Lutheran theology, that of freedom. But for a moment, lets
continue with the other keyword. Williams offers no concise definition of
religion, so we are left to our own devices. And we all know that the word
"religion" is one of the most hotly contested words on the planet. Not
only is there a global contest as to what counts as the "right"
religion, but religious studies as a discipline is almost humorously incapable
of defining the very term they study. I say almost because the academic guild,
having the task of defining religion in a "sortal" way to cover a set
of activities, way-of-being-in-the-world, tests the range of definitions and
finds them lacking, but then continuing the quest. The scholars quest for a
definition of religion aspires to objectivity and neutrality, which is a wholly
different approach than the confessional one.
You can chase the word religion down a lot of
paths. Some claim it has to do with organized forms of worship. Some argue it
is about a shared sense of meaning. Others about a higher power. Others a set
of beliefs. The problem with almost every definition offered for
"religion" is the reality that some religion of a specific group or
individual conflicts with the definition. Some religions don't organize for
worship. Other religions deny that a search for meaning is integral to their
faith. Many religions do not posit a higher power, or may be actively
anti-creedal, rejecting a body of beliefs as definitive of their religion.
This being the case, we may need to offer a
more tautological definition of religion: a religion is what is claimed as a
religion. If it's your religion, that's a religion. I offer this definition,
recognizing that this hands the definition of religion over to the participant,
whereas there are some legitimate arguments to be made for the definition of
religion remaining in the hands also of analysts of religion, even if their
definitions always fall short of completely articulating the phenomenon of
religion as we experience it.
So we can offer a somewhat concise definition
of religious liberty: Religious liberty is the hard-won freedom and privilege
to practice religion as we understand it, or as the religious analysts observe
and continually articulate it.
Of course, this itself is hotly contested.
Not all advocates for religious freedom successfully extend privileges to all
religions, and oftentimes the claims of one religion in its liberty stands in
incommensurable conflict to the religious claims of others. These are the sites
in our culture of particular heat and pain. By and large, though, I would argue that a
Lutheran understanding of religious liberty would, in its vocation to live with
and through this world, share much in common with secular or standard
understandings of the two terms, especially in our shared responsibility to
protect religious liberty in as capacious a sense as possible. Which is to say,
a working Lutheran definition of religious liberty would be to practice our
faith in such a way that the religious liberties of others are safeguarded and
even advanced as much as possible.
This brings us to the specifically Lutheran
approach to the topic. Lutherans carry with them a rather famous essay of
Martin Luther, "On Christian Liberty." In this essay, Martin Luther
offered a famous paradox:
“A Christian is a perfectly free
lord of all, subject to none.
A Christian is a perfectly
dutiful servant of all, subject of all, subject to all.”
This paradox benefits from a bit of
unpacking. First of all, Luther is working in categories of freedom related to
the things above as much as he is working in categories related to things from
below. That is, towards God, because of the justification of the ungodly in
Christ, Christians are completely free, no longer bound by their concern for
salvation, and so subject to no one as regards their standing before God. If
there is one mark of what it means to be Lutheran, it is likely this--we have
been set free from having to earn, purchase, justify, or establish in any sense
our standing before God. Christ has set us free from this. That is a form of
religious liberty. This is the freedom Luther discovered reading Paul,
Galatians and Romans in particular.
So we are freed from justifying ourselves
with God. We are realigned, new margins set, working our way down the page not
free from any margins, but free for specific margins. We are justified for the
neighbor, set at liberty, subjected to the neighbor and their need. The new
direction of concern for the Christian set free from the law is the neighbor in
love.
This bears repeating. We are set free,
liberated, for our neighbor. In this
sense, Christian liberty is not license, the liberty to do anything, but
liberation, solidarity with the neighbor so free and deep as to completely pour
the self out in neighbor love. This is why the greatest commandment, though a
law, is itself a paradoxical law, because it looses by binding.
This is where the paradox lies, because you
can't have the one without the other, even if they appear at first blush
paradoxically incompatible. Freedom can't be true freedom without love. Love
can't be love unless it is free.
As a result, I think we can offer two robust
theses regarding a specifically Lutheran understanding of religious liberty.
First, religious liberty in the Lutheran
sense will agree with the Vatican Council in Dignitatis humanae, that "a human person has a right to religious freedom.
This freedom means that all [human beings] are to be immune from coercion on
the part of individuals or of social groups and of any human power, in such
wise that no one is to be forced to act in a manner contrary to [their] own
beliefs, whether privately or publicly, whether alone or in association with
others, within due limits." So Lutherans, as ecumenically oriented
Christians open to and encouraging of shared commitments concerning religious
liberty, agree with the Roman Catholic communion that part of the recognition
of human dignity includes protection from religious coercion.
Lutherans would
take this commitment one step further. It is a step that is implied in much of Dignitatis humanae, if not expressly
conveyed. Lutherans have a habit, grounded in their Small Catechism, of
articulating an interpretation of God's commandments not simply in the
negative, but also in the affirmative. For example, Luther's explanation of the
fifth commandment, "Thou shalt not kill," reads--We should fear and love God that we
may not hurt nor harm our neighbor in their body, but help and befriend them in
every bodily need.
If we take this
same interpretive stance as regards religious liberty, Lutherans might say, a
human person should be not simply immune from coercion, but also encouraged and
supported in their religious practice. Not only are we committed to protecting
the free exercise of religion, we are also committed as Lutherans to ensuring
that all humans can practice their religion in as lively and life-giving a
manner as possible. This might take many forms in many places, but at the very
least, beyond ensuring that Muslims can build mosques and nobody at the
university has to pray to a God they don't believe in, so too Lutherans are
committed to providing the resources and space, the conversation and
neighborliness, that can make the religious liberty of their neighbor, of any
kind, as vitalized as possible.
Second, and
somewhat like the first, the Lutheran will practice their own religious liberty
in solidarity with the neighbor in their religious liberty. Lutherans have this
tradition of interpretation sometimes called the bound conscience, which
emphasizes our responsibility to recognize when the neighbor, the other, has to
stand in a place where they can "do no other," as Luther apocryphally
stated. This is to say, sometimes we discover a moment, a place, where our
neighbor's faith is particularly imperiled. I am mindful, for example, of the
recent tensions between Larycia Hawkins and Wheaton College. Here, in this
moment, a Lutheran who wishes to protect religious freedom, will strive to
understand and support the religious practices of these neighbors in faith.
In this
particular example, Lutherans might say, "Well, Larycia Hawkins is
practicing her faith, which includes her Advent discipline of embodied
spirituality, the wearing of the hijab, and Wheaton College is practicing its
religious freedom, the freedom to operate a Christian college with a specific
statement of belief expected of all faculty." Lutherans would likely also
recognize, and be particularly sympathetic to, Professor Hawkin's Advent
discipline, because it illustrates the kind of life-giving solidarity our
peculiar understanding of religious freedom entails.
Where things
would get complicated would be in the adjudication of the contesting claims for
religious freedom between the college and Professor Hawkins. It would appear
that one way or the other, somebody's religious freedom is going to be
curtailed. This is probably why Dignitatis
humanae includes that little final phrase in the quote above, "Within
due limits." There are due limits, in this life anyway, to the completely
liberated practice of anyone's or any group's religion.
This is,
specifically, the problematizing of the possible positivism I am working
against by way of an articulation of the Lutheran paradox of Christian freedom.
Personally, I do stand with and support Professor Hawkins and believe Wheaton
College is constricting her religious liberty precisely because it has the
white privilege and power to do so. The fact that she is a black woman speaking
out for solidarity with Muslims puts her in the position in need of protection.
Yet this needs to be problematized inasmuch as it is not always clear who gets
to decide who is marginalized in a given situation. That being said,
problematizing such positivism likely always carrying with it the inherent risk
of benefitting whoever happens to hold the position of power, and thus
indirectly curtailing rather than protecting religious liberty.
Take time, if
you would, to read Professor Hawkins' own case for herself over against Wheaton
College. http://drlaryciahawkins.org/2016/01/06/statement-from-16-press-conference/
In the case of
such contested claims, a Lutheran understanding of religious liberty will err
on the side of the liberty most in need of protecting. That is, solidarity will
be with the marginalized, the vulnerable, the one most at risk in the
structures of power that are at play. This is implicit in the paradox itself,
the emphasis on taking the form of the servant for the neighbor in need.
Lutherans seeking religious freedom for the neighbor will not join the group
enforcing systems that obstruct religious liberty, even if those groups
perceive their enforcement as itself an act of religious liberty. Lutherans
will stand in solidarity with the weakest and most vulnerable. They will be
servants with the servants, slaves with the slaves. Returning to Williams and
his definition of liberty, it is much more than simple emancipation--it is
winning self-determination.
The peculiar
form of Lutheran religious liberty is a sense that no self-determination need
be won on the God side of the equation, so, having already had the
self-determination won for us through the suffering love of Christ, the
Lutheran (and all Christians who share this perspective) our now free to join
the fight for self-determination for those most in need of it. This is
precisely what love looks like, in community, as it pertains to religious
freedom.
The Reverend Doctor Clint Schnekloth
Good Shepherd Lutheran Church
Fayetteville, Arkansas
ttps://www.google.com/search?q=speckhard+free+to+be+faithful&rlz=1C1CKMB_enUS570&oq=speckhard+free+to+be+faithful&aqs=chrome..69i57.8179j0j8&sourceid=chrome&es_sm=122&ie=UTF-8
ReplyDeleteNot sure if the link to Google search will work, but if you search for my name along with "free to be faithful" you'll find an essay I wrote for the LCMS that says some of the same things you're saying.